The Misdirected Quest
for Community
Why Neighborhood Ties Remain Elusive
Bruce Frohnen
When
sociologist Robert Nisbet wrote his classic Quest for
Community in 1953, he detailed the decline of extended
family, guild, church, and village. In calling attention to
the need to reinvigorate these fundamental institutions of
community life, Nisbet was a lonely voice. Today, however,
virtually everyone is lamenting the decline of strong
communities and the values they teach. From left to right on
the political spectrum, politicians, pundits, and people on
the street agree that Americans have lost touch with their
neighbors, that towns and cities lack public spirit, and
that American life and character have been impoverished by
an increasing lack of common action and feeling. The
breakdown of institutions of local life and culture is too
obvious for dispute, as are its disastrous consequences.
Whatever their political or religious views, most Americans
now recognize that high rates of divorce and out-of-wedlock
births, along with a general decline of participation in
public life, have produced a generation increasingly prone
to crime, violence, and alienation.
The new consensus embracing the importance of
community raises a simple but revealing question. If
everyone now recognizes the consequences of a loss of
community, why is so little being done to rebuild
communities or even to stop them from being destroyed? Why
do Americans allow the government at various levels to
continue tearing down neighborhoods, promoting family
breakup, and enforcing a public morality hostile to the very
habits necessary for community life? The answer begins with
the recognition that while Americans agree about the need
for community, they disagree about the nature of community
and how they should rebuild it. Further, to the extent that
they remain confused as to the intentions of the various
community boosters that have appeared on the scene a
generation after Nisbet, Americans remain vulnerable to
manipulations that can entice them into supporting policies
hostile to their most cherished beliefs, attachments, and
affections.
The leading spokesmen who praise community as an
abstract idea vary widely in their understanding of what
makes a community good or desirable. The self-described
communitarians, for example, do not even seek to rebuild
concrete communities at all. Instead they merely uphold the
language of community to cloak their attempt to politicize
American life by submitting every important question to the
machinery of politics. Another school of community boosters,
who might be called the civic renewers, seek to rebuild
communities, but only as a necessary means to reinvigorate
the public and political life they believe once flourished
in the United States. Civic renewers wish to reinvigorate
the institutions that can transform children and adults into
good citizens; their goal: a nation better able to maintain
and increase its power and vitality rather than strong and
virtuous local communities. A third school is composed of
civil renewers who add a plea for moral regeneration as the
root of free and vital public life. Recognizing that virtue
is necessary for a vibrant civic life, these moral
regenerators include religious institutions among the
civic associations they seek to reinvigorate.
Each
school of community boosters demands some form of political
revitalization. None has heeded Robert Nisbets warning
that the modern preoccupation with politics is a
self-defeating attempt to recreate the shared rituals,
practices, and comradeship once produced spontaneously by
local communities.1 None recognizes the primary role of
religion and tradition as shapers of public life. Nor does
any value religion, tradition, or community for its own
sake. All represent attempts to harness local communities to
some other end, generally a better-ordered political life.
As such, community boosters of all stripes ignore two
important realities. First, no matter how well fine tuned, a
better-ordered political life cannot stand on its own.
Second, when community and religious life is valued simply
as a means, rather than fostered for their own sake, it can
never flourish, let alone support the political life the
community boosters envision. A fuller examination of these
three major schools, coupled with an understanding of the
American tradition of faith-centered communities, explains
why the community life Americans seek today remains out of
reach. At the same time, this examination will highlight the
factors that have contributed to the decline of communities
and what is needed to rebuild them in the face of government
hostility to the very concept of a moral or traditional
community.
The Collective
Communitarian State
Communitarians
have gained visibility from their association with President
Clinton, who proudly displayed a communitarian manifesto by
Amitai Etzioni in the Oval Office, and the First Lady, who
adapted the thought of communitarian Michael Lerner in her
1993 speech at the University of Texas calling for a
politics of meaning. The concerns of
communitarians are in some cases genuine, but coming as they
do from the political left, tend to be hostile to American
traditions. Etzioni dismisses any traditional vision of
community including intact families and public
expressions of faith as an expression of nostalgia
for a Leave it to Beaver world divorced from
reality.2
Robert Bellah goes further in indicting the morality
of traditional communities, warning that a dangerously
narrow conception of social justice can result from
committing oneself to small town values.3 Bellah wants
to transform American towns into instruments of social
justice, a moral grid channeling the
energies of its enterprising citizens and their families
into collective well being. Economic democracy
collective political control over the distribution of wealth
and economic decision-making is needed to form good
communities.4
The
assumption that Americans can rebuild vital communities only
by making political action the center of their lives
represents the heart of the communitarian agenda. Bellah,
for example, praises political movements such as union
socialism because they have promoted a political
understanding of community. Suspicious both of the
massive private power that was undercutting the basis for
independent citizenship and of government without popular
control, these movements sought to use government at all
levels to bring a degree of public responsibility to the new
technologies and the wealth they generated.5 Even
moral values must be determined through political action.
Bellah dismisses talk of a crisis in family values on the
grounds that those who divorce or fail to marry are
unemployed and thus unable to get married or [do
not have] enough income to support an existing
family. Moral arguments, he believes, are useless,
even counterproductive, unless a social democracy has been
established. Rhetoric of a renewed commitment to traditional
family loyalties not only increases the level of
individual guilt, it also distracts attention from larger
failures of collective responsibilities. Not personal
morals, but collective economics that are subjected to
democratic political controls are the answer to family and
community decline.6
In
essence, communitarians do not seek to reverse the decline
of families and communities, they instead intend to replace
them with ones more to their liking. According to Bellah,
Americans must recognize innovations such as
oxymoronic homosexual marriage and the elimination of sex
roles to form good communities. Americans must also
transform religion. Bellah sees religions proper role
as aiding the process of communal recreation through
public worship. He insists that only a public church
calling for sweeping cultural and institutional
transformation toward social democracy can foster
community and spiritual fulfillment. From Zen Buddhism to
New Ageism to feminist theology, all proper religions,
according to Bellah, share hostility toward Americas
economic individualism and cultural prejudice.7 Thus
communitarians seek a radical transformation of every aspect
of life. Americans, in their view, must be transformed by
liberal experts with the proper values before good
communities can be built.
The Community of
Democratic Citizenship
The
call for community renewal certainly does not come
exclusively from the left. Indeed, many prominent figures on
the conservative end of the political spectrum have sought
civic renewal based in a reinvigoration of local
institutions and the virtues they teach. William Kristol and
William Bennett have called for a return to national
greatness and to the virtues of democratic citizenship. They
have joined with advocates of democratic community on the
left, including academics like Benjamin Barber, to serve on
the National Commission on Civic Renewal, a project funded
by the Pew Charitable Trusts.
Civic renewers take much of their rhetoric from Alexis
de Tocqueville, whose Democracy in America has
influenced American self-understanding perhaps more than any
other book. They place special emphasis on the
Frenchmans praise of local associations and his
insistence that Americans learned the habits necessary for a
free and vital public life in these associations. According
to Tocqueville, American self-reliance was, in
fact, communal:
The beginnings of this attitude first appear at
school, where the children, even in their games, submit to
rules settled by themselves and punish offenses which they
have defined themselves. The same attitude turns up again in
all the affairs of social life. If some obstacle blocks the
public road halting the circulation of traffic, the
neighbors at once form a deliberative body; this improvised
assembly produces an executive authority which remedies the
trouble before anyone has thought of the possibility of some
previously constituted authority beyond that of those
concerned.8
Rather
than an absence of authority, Tocqueville saw in America a
healthy participation in authority on the part of the
people. This participation was made possible by the plethora
of local civic associations promoting everything from
temperance to music appreciation. As Tocqueville put it,
such local, civic associations are to liberty what
primary schools are to science; they put it within the
peoples reach; they teach people to appreciate its
peaceful enjoyment and accustom them to make use of
it.9
Tocquevilles vision of America also contained a
moral dimension, understanding democracy as the best system
under contemporary conditions by which men could develop
proper moral characters.10 While William Bennett has
lamented Americans distressing inability to feel or
express
outrage at the debilitating immorality of President
Clinton,11 the morality with which most civic renewers are
concerned is political; they seek a functional morality that
has ability to command and respect democratic authority. As
critic Don Eberly notes, the goal is to temper the
publics recent repudiation of government activism by
splicing in an emphasis on civic localism. The overriding
objective, in any event, is promoting civic works, not
inspiring a moral or cultural renewal.12 Therefore,
civic renewers do not value local institutions for
themselves, but rather for their effects on the democratic
nation. William Kristol has delivered repeated calls for a
new national greatness based on a common democratic ideology
and national power in the global arena. In the same vein,
Bennett has pursued his vision of a properly, civically
educated American people through national standards seeking
to require uniform content in all schools.
The goal, for civic renewers, is a citizenry dedicated
to democracy, with the virtues necessary to support it and
spread it across the globe. The problem, as identified by
Irving Kristol, Williams father, is that men cannot
live in a free society if they have no reason to
believe it is also a just society.13 Hence, a creed of
democratic nationalism must be instilled in the young from
an early age in order to convince citizens that their
society is in fact just, and that by recognizing
individual rights and promoting political participation
it is ennobling. Yet the construct provides no reason
why citizens should value freedom and political
participation.
|